The Perilous Incoherence of Democratic Minimalism
When Truth Becomes Optional, Tyranny Becomes Inevitable
This is, after all, a philosophy blog. And as I've warned readers, in between my polemics, I do intend to try and maintain some connection back to my roots, here. So let me close this preamble with a fundamental philosophical truth: Democracy is not just a system of governance; it's an epistemological project. It's how we, as societies, grapple with reality and make collective decisions based on our best understanding of that reality.
Now, I like Shadi Hamid. I’m a regular listener of Wisdom of Crowds and a paying subscriber. Shadi often offers sharp interventions into our political malaise. But his recent defense of “democratic minimalism” is not just wrong—it’s catastrophically so. The kind of wrongness that makes you want to grab a man by the lapels and shout: Have you gone mad? Can’t you see what’s happening?
In his latest missive, Shadi backhandedly praises J.D. Vance's Munich address for its critique of European democratic backsliding, while acknowledging—with what I can only imagine is a wry smile and a raised eyebrow—the irony of such criticism coming from a representative of the Trump administration. Shadi suggests, in his infinite reasonableness, that we can and should appreciate the content of Vance's speech regardless of its source. It's as if he's proposing we judge a sermon on virtue delivered by Machiavelli purely on its rhetorical merits.
It's the sort of thing that makes one feel terribly sophisticated at cocktail parties—ah yes, we must separate the message from the messenger, mustn't we?
This view isn't just misguided; it's a kind of intellectual surrender in the face of our gravest existential threat. It fundamentally misunderstands the nature of democracy and the peril it currently faces. Democracy, my dear Shadi, is not merely a set of procedures or the abstract “right to make the wrong choice.” It is, at its core, a system for collectively discovering and contesting truth. When we sever the connection between democratic speech and a commitment to truth, we don't preserve democracy—we eviscerate it.
Shadi's framework, for all its seeming sophistication, fails to recognize that democracy rests on a shared epistemic foundation. Without a common understanding of reality, without the ability to agree on basic facts, democratic deliberation becomes not just impossible, but meaningless. When political actors systematically undermine this foundation—through lies, distortions, or the weaponization of doubt—they aren't simply expressing a different viewpoint. They're corroding the very substrate that makes meaningful democratic choice possible.
The case of Vance's Munich speech illustrates this perfectly. Here is a representative of an administration that has consistently attacked the truth-seeking mechanisms of democracy—from independent journalism to scientific institutions to the electoral process itself—lecturing others on democratic values. This isn't just hypocrisy; it's a form of democratic gaslighting that further erodes our ability to distinguish truth from manipulation. It's as if we're being asked to applaud the arsonist for his eloquent speech on fire safety while the building burns around us.
Shadi's “democratic minimalism” asks us to ignore this context, to pretend that words exist in a vacuum untouched by the actions and intentions of those who speak them. But in doing so, it strips democracy of its most essential feature: its function as a collective method for discerning reality and making decisions based on that shared understanding.
Let's be clear: Two plus two equals four. Russia invaded Ukraine. These aren't matters of opinion or perspective; they are facts, witnessed and documented. When we allow political actors to obfuscate these basic truths while simultaneously claiming to defend democratic values, we're not being open-minded or pluralistic. We're being willfully blind to the destruction of democracy itself.
The idea that shared reality can be fragmented within a democratic polity, and that this arrangement is somehow stable, defies not just logic but the very foundations of collective governance. It's a notion so absurd that one wonders if Shadi has been spending too much time in the rarefied air of think tanks, where such intellectual contortions might pass for profound insight.
To be fair, we should give a nod to Shadi's book, The Problem with Democracy, which I've also read. It's clear that Shadi's framework emerges from a genuine project to reconcile certain aspects of Islamic cultural contingencies with a desire to see a democratic renaissance in the Middle East. It's a noble aim, to be sure. To achieve this, Shadi attempts to excise liberalism from democracy, as if separating conjoined twins with a rusty hacksaw. Conceptually, one can see the appeal. Practically and ethically, it's a disaster.
Shadi's “democratic minimalism” isn't just an academic exercise; it's a dangerous flirtation with epistemic nihilism. By suggesting we can have democracy without a shared commitment to truth, he's not expanding democracy's reach—he's hollowing it out from within. It's as if he's proposing we can have a functioning circulatory system without blood, or a judicial system without laws. The very idea is not just incoherent; it's an invitation to autocracy dressed up in democratic garb.
What Shadi fails to grasp, or perhaps chooses to ignore, is that democracy isn't just about voting or the abstract right to make choices. It's a system for collective truth-seeking and decision-making. When we fragment reality, when we allow political actors to create their own facts without consequence, we're not preserving democracy—we're annihilating it. We're creating a world where power alone determines truth, where the loudest voice or the most sophisticated manipulation wins out over observable reality.
This isn't democracy; it's a perverse parody of it. It's a world where a J.D. Vance can lecture Europe on democratic values while representing an administration that has systematically attacked the very foundations of democratic truth-seeking. And Shadi, in his infinite wisdom, would have us nod along, separating the message from the messenger as if words have no context, as if truth has no meaning beyond what power declares it to be.
This is where my conception of an epistemic liberal ethic becomes not just relevant, but crucial. Unlike Shadi's minimalist framework, or even classical liberal notions of democracy mired in foundationalist ethics, the epistemic liberal ethic recognizes that democracy is fundamentally an exercise in collective epistemology. It's not just about making choices; it's about how societies discover, contest, and act upon shared truths.
The epistemic liberal ethic posits that liberalism isn't merely a set of political arrangements or individual rights. It's a sophisticated system for societal truth-seeking. Free speech, independent institutions, protected dissent—these aren't just nice ideas or moral imperatives. They're the machinery through which human societies process reality and make decisions based on our best understanding of that reality.
Shadi's framework, in its attempt to divorce democracy from liberalism, misses this crucial point. It treats democracy as if it were merely a mechanism for aggregating preferences, ignoring the vital role that liberal institutions play in ensuring those preferences are informed, contestable, and grounded in a shared reality. This isn't just a philosophical quibble; it's a fundamental misunderstanding of how democracies function and persist.
Consider the implications: In Shadi's world, we could have a “democracy” where different factions operate with entirely different sets of facts, where truth is whatever those in power declare it to be, where the mechanisms for challenging falsehoods have been dismantled in the name of cultural accommodation. This isn't democracy; it's a recipe for perpetual conflict, manipulation, and ultimately, autocracy.
The epistemic liberal ethic, by contrast, recognizes that democracy requires more than just voting booths and the abstract right to dissent. It requires a shared commitment to reality-based governance, to institutions that can arbitrate competing truth claims, to processes that allow for the revision of beliefs in light of new evidence. Without these liberal underpinnings, democracy becomes a hollow shell, easily manipulated by those with the power to control information and shape narratives.
Shadi's framework, well-intentioned as it may be, falls far short of providing a viable model for democratic governance. It's not just that it's less sophisticated than the epistemic liberal ethic; it's that it fundamentally misunderstands the nature of democratic legitimacy and stability. A democracy that cannot distinguish truth from falsehood, that cannot hold power accountable to reality, is no democracy at all. It's a waiting room for tyranny, dressed up in the language of choice and cultural respect.
Shadi's democratic minimalism, in its myopic focus on the mere act of choice, conveniently ignores the critical question of how those choices are formed. It's as if he's content to watch a magician's trick without ever asking how it's done, and then declaring the audience's amazement as the only thing that matters.
Yes, the fact that a majority might support something certainly carries ethical weight. But to treat that support as sacrosanct without examining its origins is not just naive—it's dangerous. It's a perspective that would have us respect the “democratic choice” of a populace systematically deceived by sophisticated propaganda, manipulated by opaque algorithmic systems, or coerced through more traditional forms of power.
Consider the implications: In Shadi's framework, a majority deceived into supporting its own subjugation would be, what? A triumph of democracy? A regrettable but legitimate outcome? This is where the incoherence of his position becomes not just apparent, but alarming.
The epistemic liberal ethic, by contrast, recognizes that the “why” behind majority support is not just important—it's essential. It understands that democracy is not merely about counting votes, but about the process through which citizens form their views, access information, and engage in collective deliberation. When these processes are corrupted—whether by deliberate propaganda, manipulative social media algorithms, or other forms of deception—the resulting “choice” is not a democratic outcome. It's a perversion of democracy.
Shadi's minimalism offers no tools to ethically engage with this reality. It provides no mechanism to distinguish between a majority formed through open debate and shared truth-seeking, and one manufactured through systematic deception. In doing so, it not only fails to protect democracy—it actively enables its subversion.
The epistemic liberal ethic, however, gives us a framework to address these challenges. It insists that democratic legitimacy rests not just on the act of voting, but on the integrity of the entire democratic process—including how information is shared, how debates are conducted, and how citizens are empowered to seek and contest truth.
In a world where technology enables unprecedented manipulation of public opinion, where AI can generate convincing falsehoods at scale, and where social media algorithms can create hermetically sealed realities, Shadi's minimalism is worse than useless—it's complicit. It would have us respect the “democratic will” of a populace living in a manufactured reality, as if the mere act of voting could launder the ethical taint of systematic deception.
This is not to say that the epistemic liberal ethic offers easy answers. Distinguishing legitimate persuasion from manipulation, separating good-faith disagreement from deliberate disinformation—these are complex challenges. But unlike Shadi's framework, it at least acknowledges that these distinctions matter, that the why behind majority support is crucial to democratic legitimacy.
In the end, Shadi's democratic minimalism isn't just ethically incoherent—it's a capitulation to the very forces threatening democracy. It offers no defense against the sophisticated tools of modern authoritarianism, no way to resist the slide into technologically enabled despotism. It asks us to respect the choices of a populace that may no longer be choosing freely at all.
When we sever the link between democracy and truth-seeking, we don't preserve freedom—we pave the way for its destruction.
If you are able to withstand Shadi Hamid's infuriating needle threading you are made of sterner stuff than me.
“In an ever-changing, incomprehensible world the masses had reached the point where they would, at the same time, believe everything and nothing, think that everything was possible and that nothing was true. ... Mass propaganda discovered that its audience was ready at all times to believe the worst, no matter how absurd, and did not particularly object to being deceived because it held every statement to be a lie anyhow. The totalitarian mass leaders based their propaganda on the correct psychological assumption that, under such conditions, one could make people believe the most fantastic statements one day, and trust that if the next day they were given irrefutable proof of their falsehood, they would take refuge in cynicism; instead of deserting the leaders who had lied to them, they would protest that they had known all along that the statement was a lie and would admire the leaders for their superior tactical cleverness.”
― Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism